ENZO TRAVERSO is the author of several books on German and European history, including The Origins of Nazi Violence (2003), Understanding the Nazi Genocide (1999) and Marxists and the Jewish Question: The History of a Debate, 1843-1943 (1994).
WE ARE WITNESSING TODAY a paradoxical and unsettling phenomenon: the rise of fascist-inspired political movements in the European arena (from France to Italy, from Belgium to Austria), accompanied, in the heart of intellectual circles, by a massive campaign to denigrate the entire anti-fascist tradition. In Italy, the media presents anti-fascism as being responsible for the catastrophic shifts of the "first Republic"; while the main biographer of Mussolini, Renzo De Felice, has led a battle to overcome the "anti-fascist paradigm," which is, according to him, the major defect of post-war historiography.1 In Germany, since the reunification, the appellative "anti-fascist" is used as an insult, in more or less deliberately forgetting all that anti-fascism represented, for the German exile and for the struggle against Hitler's regime, before it was transformed into the state ideology of the German Democratic Republic.2
In France, the
campaign against anti-fascism was launched a few years ago by Annie Kriegel's article in
Commentaire.3 It experienced
its lowest moment during the publication of a vile pamphlet that tried to present Jean Moulin as a
Soviet spy,4 and its crowning moment, on a
much higher cultural plane, with François Furet's Le passé d'une
illusion, a book in which anti-fascism is reduced to a giant enterprise of mystification that
allowed Soviet totalitarianism to extend its influence over Western culture.5
What is at stake
is important: what remains of the intellectuals' anti-fascist involvement? Can we, today, call
ourselves anti-fascists? Those who are convinced, as I am, of the historical value and of the
political relevance of anti-fascism, and thus of the necessity to fight a harmful form of revisionism,
cannot allow themselves to answer these questions by hiding behind an apologetic idealization of
the past. One would be tempted to respond that, by ridding oneself of anti-fascism, one risks
effacing the only decent face that Italy was able to put on between 1922 and 1945, Germany
between 1933 and 1945, France between 1940 and 1944, Spain and Portugal for almost forty
years. But, although necessary, this answer is not enough. To defend anti-fascism as an
"exemplary" memory, in the noblest sense of the word, and as a still-living lesson of the past, one
must proceed to its critical historization, by grasping the weaknesses and limits that often go
hand-in-hand with its greatness. And to understand the intellectuals' relationship to anti-fascism,
one must delve deep into the sources of their involvement.
One of George
Orwell's last essays, "Writers and Leviathan," is devoted to the relationship that took shape in
Europe during the 1930s between intellectuals and politics. In it, he emphasizes (starting for the
most part from an autobiographical reflection) the almost inevitable nature of the irruption of
politics into culture. Writers were no longer able to shut themselves up in a universe of aesthetic
values, sheltered from the conflicts that were tearing apart the old world. "No one, now, could
devote himself to literature as single-mindedly as Joyce or Henry James," he wrote.6 The same reckoning had already been made, a
dozen years earlier, just before the war, by Walter Benjamin, who affirmed the necessity of
contrasting the politicization of art and culture -- and the involvement of artists and intellectuals --
with the aesthetization of politics implemented by fascism:
Fiat ars, pereat mundus: that's the word of command of fascism, which, as Marinetti recognizes, expects from war the artistic satisfaction of a sensory perception altered by technology. That is obviously the perfect realization of art for art's sake. During Homer's time, humanity made itself a spectacle for the gods of Olympus; now it has made itself its own spectacle. It has become alien enough to itself to succeed in living its own destruction like some aesthetic enjoyment of the first order. That is the kind of aesthetization of politics practiced by fascism. Communism's response is to politicize art.7
In other words,
the intellectual had to "stick his neck out," to scrape against the asperities of the present, to
become in his way "militant" if he did not want to stagnate like a fossil, like an anachronistic and
useless figure of the man of letters living outside his time.
THE NOTION OF THE "INTELLECTUAL," which definitively enters Western vocabulary during the Dreyfus affair, designates precisely that mutual interference between literature and politics that will profoundly mark the entire history of the twentieth century. Of course, this figure does not lack illustrious precedents, from the philosophers of the Enlightenment to the revolutions of 1848, in which a number of men of letters participated. But it is only with the turn of the century that this phenomenon takes on new dimensions, till it becomes, during the period between the two wars, a major aspect of European and Western culture. In The Treason of the Intellectuals (La Trahison des clercs), Julien Benda tried to capture this image of the engaged man of letters with an ideal- typical definition: "men whose function is that of defending eternal and disinterested values, like justice and reason."8
Upon close
inspection, though, intellectuals' entry into politics was not always based on these values. Already
the Dreyfus affair was an intellectuals' dispute: Maurice Barrès against Emile Zola,
Edouard Drumont against Bernard-Lazare. In other words, nationalism against universalism, anti-
Semitism against equality, militarism against the republic. During the 1920s and 1930s, these
conflicts were to become more pronounced: besides the intellectuals who mobilized to defend
democracy, there were others who worked to destroy it. A large part of European culture adhered
to values that contradict those of the revolutionary tradition of 1789. Nationalism, anti-Semitism,
the "conservative revolution," anti-democratic elitism and fascism all exercised a considerable
attraction on a great number of intellectuals in Italy, in France, in Germany, and even in a
traditional seat of liberalism like England.9
One often tends to forget them, out of a kind of retrospective overlap that hides the fact that
Gramsci became a central figure of Italian culture only after the war and the fall of fascism, that
Maurras and Drieu la Rochelle were just as influential, in France in the 1930s, as Malraux and
Gide, and that, under the Weimar Republic, Ernst Jünger was just as famous as Erich Maria
Remarque, and Oswald Spengler was much more widely read than Walter Benjamin or Ernst
Bloch.
A literary
prefiguration of this dichotomy -- the democratic, rationalistic, anti-fascist intellectual on the one
hand, on the other the romantic and apocalyptic nihilist, rebelling against modernity -- was
portrayed by Thomas Mann, in the beginning of the 1920s, in The Magic Mountain.
The two heroes of this novel, Settembrini and Naphta, have been interpreted as the two souls of
the author, who had published, at the close of WWI, a manifesto of the "conservative revolution"
under the title Reflections of a Non-Political Man, and who was to go on to embody
the democratic consciousness of his country when, exiled in the United States, he launched his
"Summons to the Germans" (broadcast by the BBC) to denounce the crimes of National
Socialism. Others have seen in it a literary transfiguration of the dialogue that Mann had begun
with his brother Heinrich, whose philosophy is close to Settembrini's humanist positivism. More
recently, this novelistic conflict, set by the author in the heart of the Swiss Alps, on the eve of
WWI, has been evoked as the prefiguration of another famous philosophical dispute, this time
entirely real, that took place in Davos, in 1929, between the last representative of the German
Aufklärung, the Neo-Kantian Ernst Cassirer, and Martin Heidegger, the young
author of Being and Time, founder of a new form of political ontology that would
lead him, a few years later, to accept the Nazi regime.10
The parabola of
the European intelligentsia of the interwar period unfolds between these two philosophical and
political poles, ones that are indeed opposite, but not always without shared viewpoints. Some
critics have even formulated the hypothesis that the portrayal of the nihilist Naphta was inspired in
Thomas Mann by the young Georg Lukàcs, author of Soul and Form, who
was attracted, near the end of the war, by Communism to the point of becoming, in 1919,
People's Commissar in the Ministry of Education in the ephemeral Hungarian Soviet Republic led
by Bela Kun.11 As a romantic, Naphta is
a kind of two-headed Janus, one conservative, even reactionary, the other revolutionary. This
metaphorical figure serves here to remind us that many of the intellectuals -- often Jewish and
anti-fascist -- who were destined to play a considerable role in the revitalization of post-war
political philosophy were themselves students of Heidegger. One has merely to think of Hannah
Arendt and Hans Jonas, or even of the Marxists Herbert Marcuse and Günther Anders. The
fact is that, during the 1930s, Naphta had to choose: his rejection of Zivilisation could
shelter either in the teutonic mythologies cultivated by National Socialism, to the point of
accepting the mysticism of blood and soil, or in the radical criticism of the face of modernity
embodied by fascism.12
If the "engaged"
intellectual, the rebellious humanist portrayed by Benda "situated in his time,"
according to the definition Sartre will give of him a few years later -- is far from taking up all the
terrain during the first half of the century, he will nonetheless experience a considerable increase
in popularity during the thirties. The great turningpoint that marks the political involvement of the
intellectuals is not 1917, the October revolution, but 1933, when Hitler came to power in
Germany. This engagement often coincides, it is true, with their entry into the magnetic field of
Communism, which however does not constitute the point of departure but only the result of their
radicalization. In 1917, John Reed, for whom the Russian Soviets were going to "shake the
world," remains an exception. In 1934, on the other hand, Heinrich Mann is far from being
isolated when he publishes Hatred. At the end of the First World War, Louis Aragon,
the future eulogist of Stalin and official poet of French Communism, had reduced the October
Revolution to a simple "ministerial crisis." No one could react with the same offhandedness faced
with Nazism. After 1933, the anti-fascist involvement of intellectuals was to be massive. It would
lead many of those who had remained indifferent or who had not hidden their skepticism when
faced with the workers' uprisings in Turin, Berlin and Budapest in 1919-1920, to approach the
Soviet Union, perceived as a rampart against the rise of the brown plague in Europe.
THIS ANTI-FASCIST MOBILIZATION would be marked, between 1935 and 1937, by two international conferences in defense of culture: the first was held in Paris, the second in Valencia, in republican Spain, in which some of the most significant cultural figures of the time participated.13 It would reach its peak during the Spanish Civil War, when defense of the Republic came to be identified with the defense of European culture. Numerous writers enrolled in the international brigades or went to Spain to support the Republic, from George Orwell to Ernest Hemingway, from André Malraux to Arthur Koestler, from W.H. Auden to Stephen Spender, from Benjamin Péret to Octavio Paz. The alliance between the anti-fascist intelligentsia and communism would be sustained for a long time, weakened by the Russo-German pact of 1939, then renewed in 1941 and sealed by the resistance. In 1945, European culture was, to a great extent, set under the banner of anti-fascism.
Several elements
were at the source of this political turning point for the intellectuals.14 First of all, Hitler's rise to power in Germany -- followed a year
later by the clerical-fascist coup d'état of Dolfuss in Austria, then by Franco's
pronunciamiento in Spain -- was experienced as a real trauma. Though Italian fascism
remained a national phenomenon, isolated, unknown and misunderstood, which could even win
over an important sector of Italian culture, from D'Annunzio to Gentile, and even of its avant-
garde (the Futurists), the advent of National Socialism to Germany suddenly gave fascism a
European dimension, by making it look like a terrible threat, not just for the worker's movement
but, more generally, for democracy and culture throughout the continent. This threat was not
limited to the political sphere, for it seemed to call civilization itself into question. One had only to
listen to the declarations of Nazi leaders to understand that the inheritance of the Enlightenment
was in danger: Goebbels did in fact announce that "the year 1789 will be crossed out of
history."15
Anti-fascism
was also identified with the struggle for peace, in a continent where the wounds from the First
World War were still open, and where the political balances seemed increasingly more precarious.
The Italian attack on Ethiopia, the re-militarization of the Rhineland, the war in Spain, the Sino-
Japanese war, then Munich and finally a new war: this escalation aroused an increasing anxiety
whose echo was felt in art and culture. Last but not least, fascism had made intellectuals one of its
favorite targets, as attested by the thousands of writers, journalists, scientists, academics and
artists forced to emigrate. The anti-fascist culture was also, to a very great extent, a culture of
exile. Its unity was cemented by a crowd of outcasts wandering from one country to another,
from one continent to another, like the ambassadors of a humanist Europe threatened with
annihilation. Anti-fascism also expressed itself thanks to a pleiad of German-language journals
published in Paris, London, Prague, Zurich, Amsterdam, Moscow and New York by exiles from
Central Europe, most of them Jewish. All these intellectuals, Peter Gay has written, contributed to
giving to the spirit of Weimar "its true home: exile."16
Many critics
have emphasized the limits of this anti-fascist involvement, often as generous as it was blind. It
wasn't just the "organic" intellectuals and the fellow-travelers of Communist groups that refused
to see the tyrannical aspects of Stalinism. André Gide's Return from the
USSR, George Orwell's Homage to Catalonia, Victor Serge's
Midnight in the Century, and Arthur Koestler's Darkness at Noon, all
published between 1936 and 1940, are exceptions, unnoticed upon their publication or soon
forgotten -- like Gide's book -- after an ephemeral sensation. The general tone of anti-fascism with
regard to the Soviet regime was rather one of a certain complacency, if not of an uncritical
admiration. During the Paris Congress of 1935, Magdeline Paz and Henri Poulaille found it
difficult to present an appeal in favor of the libertarian writer Victor Serge, deported to
Siberia.17 With regard to the USSR, the
dominant attitude was not that of Gide or Orwell, but of the Fabian socialists Sidney and Beatrice
Webb, two intellectuals fundamentally foreign to Communism by tradition, culture, and
temperament, who nonetheless published Soviet Communism: A New Civilization
(1935); or of the German writer Lion Feuchtwanger, who was present at the Moscow trials and
who approved of them enthusiastically in Moscow 1937.
But one did not
necessarily have to convert to the cult of Stalin, after 1933, to defend the USSR. Anti-fascism
cannot be reduced to a simple variation of Soviet Communism. In The Passing of an
Illusion, on the other hand, François Furet stigmatizes "the completely negative idea
of 'anti-fascism'" as product of the "great Comintern turning point of 1935," with which, thanks to
a clever mystification, Russian totalitarianism is supposed to have disguised itself as a herald of
democracy.18
This thesis
simplifies historical reality for at least two reasons. On the one hand, it erases all the non- and
even anti-Stalinist tendencies acting in the heart of anti-fascist culture; on the other, it seems to
ignore the fact that, in western Europe, one could not fight fascism by opposing or doing without
the support of the Communists and of the Soviet Union. To ignore these facts can lead only to
dangerous detours, as a lucid figure of liberal anti-fascism, Norberto Bobbio, recently pointed out:
"Over these last years of historic revisionism, I have come to note with bitterness that the
rejection of anti-fascism in the name of anti-communism has often led to another form of
equidistance that seems to me abominable: the one between fascism and anti-fascism."19
The turning
point of the Comintern, in 1935, did not determine but fitted into a turning point that had already
begun, in the worker's movement as well as in the intellectual world, in 1933. In France, the first
appeal for unity of action against fascism followed by a few days the riots of February 6, 1934. It
is signed by the Surrealists (André Breton, René Crevel and Paul éluard)
and by writers attracted to Communism like Jean-Richard Bloch and André Malraux. A
few days later, a similar appeal launched by the philosopher Alain and the ethnologists Paul Rivet
and Paul Langevin, obtained several thousand signatures in a few months. A Comité
de vigilance des intellectuels antifascistes (CVIA)20 thus took shape. In short, far from constituting a subproduct, the
anti-fascism of the intellectuals precedes the adoption of a policy of the Popular Front by the
Communist Party and the SFIO (Section française de l'internationale
ouvrière).
The alliance
between the representatives of European culture and Communism is the product of fascism. The
inability or unwillingness to see the true face of Stalinism is all the more intensified when the
threat of fascism is great, immediate, terrible. Rare, in Europe, were any anti-fascists ready to
denounce Stalin's crimes, or who understood that though the Communists were allies in the
struggle against fascism, their policies should not be supported, and that the anti-fascist struggle
itself risks being vitiated if one passes over in silence Soviet despotism, the trials, the summary
executions, the deportations, the camps (to say nothing of forced collectivization, ignored at the
time even by the most virulent anti-Communist literature). That was the course followed by the
Surrealists who, in 1936, denounced the Moscow trial as "an abject police production," and by the
intellectual milieu that had gathered in New York around the Partisan Review, over
which Trotsky exercised a certain influence, and which supported an investigating committee,
presided over by John Dewey, that aimed to unmask these show trials.21 We could add the names of Communist intellectuals who broke
with Stalinism, from Paul Nizan to Manes Sperber, from Arthur Koestler to Willy
Münzenberg.
During his
intervention at the Congress for the Freedom of Culture, in 1935, the Italian anti-fascist Gaetano
Salvemini, exiled at the time in the United States, very explicitly expressed his reservations with
regard to Stalinism, and thus aroused, as Breton had before him, the disapproval of a large part of
the public: "I would not have the right to protest against the Gestapo and the fascist Ovra," he
asserted, "if I tried to forget that a Soviet police-court policy exists. In Germany there are
concentration camps, in Italy there are islands transformed into places of detention, and in Soviet
Russia there is Siberia."22
In addition, the
theory of totalitarianism (putting Stalin's Russia and Hitler's Germany side by side, like two forms
of a new absolutism), whose first formulations were elaborated by some ex-Communist essayists
(Franz Borkenau) or conservative-liberals (Eric Voegelin and Waldemar Gurian, then Friedrich
Hayek and others) was perceived much more as the sign of a retreat of intellectuals towards an
attitude of skeptical passivity and impotent pessimism than as an example of a more effective and
lucid involvement. The theoreticians of totalitarianism did indeed grasp the despotic nature of
Stalin's regime, but the logical conclusion implicit in their thesis -- the impossibility of an alliance
with the USSR -- became, after 1941, completely unreal. They themselves, beginning with
Raymond Aron, refused to draw such a conclusion. Not until the beginning of the Cold War could
the concept of totalitarianism be legitimized within the political culture of the western world in
order to defend the "free world" against Soviet communism. But during World War II, such an
attitude could never have been accepted.
This infernal
dialectics between fascism and Stalinism explains to a great extent, without justifying it, the
silence of many intellectuals about the crimes of Stalinism. First the threat of fascism, and then the
immense prestige and historical legitimacy acquired by the USSR during the Second World War,
led a considerable part of western culture to ignore, underestimate, exculpate and even legitimize
the Soviet regime. The examples cited above of the Surrealists, of the New York intellectuals and
of other independent socialists prove that it was possible to be both anti-fascist and anti-Stalin,
and that the fascination exercised at the time by Stalinism on the anti-fascist intelligentsia was not
irresistible.
Furet, on the
other hand, contrasts the beneficial virtues of a liberalism historically innocent and politically
clairvoyant, a true antithesis of totalitarianisms, with the anti-fascism of the intellectuals. His
vision of anti-fascism is as unilateral as his apology for liberalism is ahistorical. One of the
conditions for the political radicalization and the adherence of intellectuals to Communism, in the
context of economic depression and the rise of fascism, resides precisely in the historical crisis of
classical liberalism. Left shaken and weakened by the First World War as well as undermined by
nationalist pressures, liberal-conservative institutions were fundamentally incapable of opposing
fascism. If fascism had been begotten by the collapse of the old liberal-conservative order, how
could one identify with this order to fight its monstrous progeny?
If fascism buried
liberal democracy, it did so by attacking first the left, the worker's movement, then the Jews and
other "anti-national elements," not by calling into question the traditional elite that had established
its power in the framework of liberal institutions. Can we forget the adherence to fascism of all
the pillars of Italian conservative liberalism: the monarchy, the bourgeoisie and even a
considerable part of intellectual society (Vilfredo Pareto and Giovanni Gentile, even including,
until 1925, Benedetto Croce)? Can we forget Winston Churchill's praise of Mussolini? Can we
forget the thoroughness with which, between 1930 and 1933, the Prussian elite rid themselves of
their façade of liberalism and dismantled the democracy of Weimar while preparing for
Hitler's accession? In such a context, in western Europe, the USSR seemed much more apt to
block fascism than the traditional forces of a deliquescent liberalism.23
Of course, we
can reproach the intellectuals who upheld the myth of the USSR with having lied to themselves
and contributed to deceiving the anti-fascist movement, whose critical conscience they could have
respected instead of making themselves the propagandists of a despotic regime. But we can be
certain that no mass mobilization against the Nazi threat could have come into being under the
guidance of the old conservative politicians.
The struggle
against fascism needed a hope, a liberating and universal message that the land of the 1917
revolution seemed to offer. If a totalitarian dictatorship like Stalin's could embody these values in
the eyes of millions of men and women -- that is indeed the tragedy of Communism in the
twentieth century -- it is precisely because its nature and its origins were profoundly different from
those of fascism. That is what liberal anti-totalitarianism seems fundamentally incapable of
understanding.
WHAT IS MORE DIFFICULT TO FATHOM, however, is the silence of anti-fascist intellectuals faced with another chasm in the twentieth century, Auschwitz. The genocide of the Jews in Europe -- an extermination that was meant to be total, with no exceptions -- was not foreseeable. Many historians are inclined to think, rather, that Hitler was not acting according to a carefully-laid strategy, and that his radical anti-Semitism came to be transformed into a genocidal plan only in the terrible conditions of the war in the East, which was a war of conquest and annihilation. The fact remains that, from 1933 onward, a heavy threat weighed on the Jews, even if no one could yet grasp its catastrophic outcome. The emigration of about 400,000 Jews from central Europe, between Hitler's accession to power and the outbreak of the war, revealed the gravity of this threat in an unquestionable way.
Yet all through
the 1930s anti-Semitism was never perceived by anti-fascist intellectuals as one of the founding
elements, even as the "central issue" of the Nazi system, but rather as the simple propagandist
corollary of a regime that had chosen for its enemies democracy, liberalism, Marxism and the
worker's movement, the crushing of which had moreover been one of its first steps, if not its very
conditions for existence. Few intellectuals had the clairvoyance of Gershon Scholem who, three
months after Hitler's coming into power, wrote from Palestine to his friend Walter Benjamin,
exiled in France, a letter in which he defined the advent of Nazism as "a catastrophe of a
worldwide historical dimension": "The proportions of the defeat of the socialist and Communist
movements in our eyes take on a sinister and unsettling aspect," he wrote, "but the defeat of
German Judaism truly beggars comparison."24 In another letter to Benjamin, in February 1940, Scholem posed
the crucial question: "what will happen to Europe after the elimination of the Jews?"25
Just after the
war, the final solution appeared as just one of its tragic pages among many others, and occupied
only a marginal place in intellectual discourse. The dominant attitude was that of silence.
Auschwitz was neither the Dreyfus affair nor the Spanish Civil War, nor was it Vietnam, events
that triggered intellectuals' debate and to which they reacted by taking on their "responsibilities."
Sartre's Réflexions sur la question juive [translated by George J. Becker as
Anti-Semite and Jew], published in 1946, is a revealing example of this "blindness of
scholars" faced with Auschwitz. Sartre designates the Jews as the forgotten victims of the war,
but he never places their genocide in the center of his thinking. Even after the Nazi extermination
camps, in his eyes the "Jewish question" remains the French anti-Semitism of the Dreyfus Affair
and of the Third Republic. This famous essay, in which the gas chambers are scarcely mentioned,
and then in a completely marginal way, could easily be interpreted as the most significant
testimony to the blindness of European culture facing one of the greatest tragedies of the century.
But Sartre's example is far from unique.26
This blindness
had of course profound causes, stemming as much from the general context of the war -- despite
its specificities, the suffering of the Jews formed part of a huge massacre that spared almost no
nation, and its visibility was reduced in a continent in ruins -- as from an older lack of
understanding of the nature of Nazi anti-Semitism, which was thought of as an obscurantist and
medieval holdover, not as a form of reactionary modernism. It was, according to a stereotype that
dated back to the socialist culture of the nineteenth century, "the socialism of fools," that is to say
a simple propaganda weapon. An industrial and bureaucratic genocide was an absolute novelty
whose possibility was not reckoned in the categories of anti-fascist culture.27
Under
Mussolini's and Hitler's regimes, the latter retained only its "regressive" and purely negative
characteristics: anti-liberalism, anti-communism, anti-individualism, anti-parliamentarianism, anti-
rationalism. Fascism is thus reduced exclusively to its reactionary aspect. Rare are those who
discern the roots of fascist movements in industrial society, in the mobilization of the masses, in
the cult of technology -- those, in short, who recognize fascism as a reactionary variation of
modernity. There is nothing more puzzling, on the ideological level, than fascist movements, a
nebulous assemblage in which conservatism and eugenics, futurism and neoclassicism, cultural
pessimism and "conservative revolution," spiritualism and anti-Semitism, regressive romanticism
and technocratic totalitarianism all cohabit; in other words, an eclectic magma where we find
Georges Valois and Alfred Rosenberg, Filippo T. Marinetti and Arno Brecker, Julius Evola and
Albert Speer, Oswald Spengler and Ernst Jünger, Giovanni Gentile and Carl Schmitt.
This jumble of
contradictory sensibilities hid the nature of fascisms as "revolutionary" regimes, whose rejection
of liberal and democratic modernity aimed not for a return to a bygone era but to the
establishment of a new order, hierarchical, authoritarian, non-egalitarian, nationalistic, even racial,
but not backward-looking: fascist mysticism is biologized, its cult of technology aesthetisized, its
scorn for democracy founded on the mobilization of the masses, and its rejection of individualism
proclaimed in the name of a "community of the people," sealed by war.
It is impossible,
however, to grasp the modernity of fascism on the basis of a philosophy of history postulating the
evolution of humanity toward the ineluctable triumph of reason. An important characteristic of
anti-fascism, which helps to explain its complacency with respect to Stalinism as well as its
blindness before the genocide of the Jews, lies in its stubborn defense of the idea of progress, one
of the great categories inherited from the European culture of the nineteenth century. "Men and
women of the resistance," wrote James D. Wilkinson in The Intellectual Resistance in
Europe, "resemble their spiritual ancestors of the eighteenth century, the
philosophers."28 The plethora of journals
that appear or are revived in 1945 -- Esprit, Les Temps modernes,
Critique in France, Der Ruf and Der Anfang in Germany,
Il Ponte, Belfagor and Nuovo Politecnico in Italy -- claim
explicitly to follow this humanist rationalism embodied by Lessing, Voltaire and Cattaneo. The
return to liberty and democracy is experienced as a new triumph of the Enlightenment, of reason
and law, which makes fascism seem a parenthesis to history, an ephemeral regression, an
anachronistic and absurd relapse into an ancestral barbarism, a failed attempt to stop the march of
humanity toward peace and progress.
In this climate of
confidence in the future, in which history seems finally reinstalled on its natural tracks, no one
worries about the survivors of the Nazi extermination camps. No one wants to listen to their
story, and Primo Levi encountered the greatest difficulties when he tried to publish Se
questo è un uomo (If This Is a Man, published in America as
Survival in Auschwitz), which was rejected in 1947 by Einaudi, the most prestigious
of the anti-fascist publishing houses in Italy. The Soviet Union, on the other hand, profited from
the price it had to pay to conquer the Third Reich. The struggle for progress was identified with
the fight to defend the fatherland of socialism. The spirit of the time had been anticipated, on the
eve of the war by the philosopher Alexandre Kojève, who, during a conversation with
Roger Caillois, thought he saw in Stalin, as Hegel before had seen in Napoleon in Jena, the Spirit
of the world, the man of the end of History.29
For Theodor
Adorno, however, National Socialism was a refutation of Hegel's philosophy of history. In 1944,
he in turn believed he had encountered the spirit of the world (Weltgeist), not on
horseback, or in the form of a Soviet tank, but in the Hitlerian V-2s, the robot bombs which,
following the example of fascism, "combine a total blindness with the most advanced technical
perfection."30 Adorno's philosophical
position is the same as the Frankfurt School, which brings together one of the most significant
movements of German anti-fascist exile. Jews without a country and "without attachments," its
leaders participated in the anti-fascist movement while still remaining at its fringes, aware that,
despite its defeat, Nazism had already changed the face of the century and the image of mankind.
The feeling of a definitive annihilation, that of the Jewish world of central Europe, permeates the
writings of the Judeo-German intelligentsia in exile. Auschwitz seemed to them a caesura in
history, like "a quasi-total rupture," Hannah Arendt writes in The Origins of
Totalitarianism, "in the uninterrupted flow of western history as man had known it for more
than two millennia."31
For the
intellectuals of the Frankfurt School, recognition of Auschwitz as a rupture in civilization is
inseparable from a radical calling into question of the idea of progress. If Nazism tried to erase the
humanist inheritance of the Enlightenment, it must also be understood, dialectically, as a product
of western civilization itself, with its technological and instrumental rationality henceforth free of
any emancipatory aim and reduced to a plan of domination. In this perspective, Auschwitz can be
apprehended neither as "regression" nor as parenthesis, but rather as an authentic product of the
west, as the emergence of its destructive face. In 1944, Horkheimer and Adorno perceive
Auschwitz as the symbol of a "self-destruction of reason."32 Exiled to the United States, Günther Anders was one of
the first, along with Albert Camus and Georges Bataille in France, to consider Hiroshima as the
founding event of a new era in which humanity is irrevocably in a position to self-
destruct.33 Far from celebrating a new
triumph of the Enlightenment, these isolated figures cannot think of the war as a victorious epic of
progress. Before the spectacle of a civilization that transformed modern technology into a "fetish
of decadence" (Benjamin), the only feeling possible is shame, a "Promethean shame" (Anders) as
great as the extent of the disaster.
IF ONE WANTED TO DRAW UP a critical balance-sheet of the anti-fascist involvement of intellectuals during the 1930s and 1940s, it is this fundamentally pessimistic way of thinking, quite marginal in the European culture into which it introduces a dialectical, melancholic and desperate dissonance, that seems to me the most interesting and lucid one today. The profundity of these intellectuals' gaze stemmed also from their isolation, the price of which was an almost complete invisibility and powerlessness, which could only accentuate their despair.
This lucidity,
favored by exile, presupposed a detachment, a critical distancing, which was not granted to those
who, in Europe, were involved in the struggle. Here, where the anti-fascist fight was identified
with hope for a new world, the intellectuals' state of mind was different. Indeed, in this fight they
were neither the most numerous nor the most generous. The partisans' guerilla warfare -- need we
be reminded? -- was made up of proletarians, rarely of writers. Among the latter, some chose
collaboration, others opted for different forms, more or less comfortable, of "adaptation,"34 but their participation in anti-fascist resistance
was not negligible. They indeed were the ones who shaped the culture of the resistance, who
wrote for its press, who gave it its color and its style. For a little while, they truly embodied, in the
eyes of the world, the universal values of justice and reason that Benda had spoken of fifteen
years earlier. That is why the memory of those who chose to fight against fascism, with their pens
and often with weapons, should be preserved. It is also thanks to thousands of intellectuals,
Communist or not, anonymous or famous, who were shot, who died in combat, in a prison or
concentration camp, if the air we breathe today is freer than that of the Europe that swallowed
them up.
If we do not
think of democracy as a simple procedural norm -- according to the vision of Hans Kelsen and
Norberto Bobbio -- but as an historical conquest, we should deduce from this that it
is impossible to be democratic, at this end of the twentieth century, without being at the same time
anti-fascist. A "non-anti-fascist" democracy would be fragile indeed, a luxury that continental
Europe, which was well acquainted with Hitler, Mussolini and Franco, cannot allow
itself.35 That is a lesson that the history
of the intellectual anti-fascist resistance should have taught us, clearly and definitively.
Translated from the French by Charlotte Mandell